Skip to main content

Section 16.4 Algebraic Closures

“I think sometimes people really requite the satisfaction of closure.”
―Diablo Cody

Subsection Clooooosing Time

Definition 16.59. Algebraic Closure.

A field \(L\) is algebraically closed if every non-constant polynomial \(f(x) \in L[x]\) has a root in \(L.\)

Example 16.60. \(\C\) is algebraically closed.

\(\C\) is algebraically closed. This is the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra.

Proof.

  1. \(\Rightarrow\) (2): Given a non-constant \(f(x) \in L[x]\text{,}\) by assumption \(f\) has a root \(a \in L\) and thus \(f(x) = (x - a)g(x)\) with \(g(x) \in L[x]\text{.}\) But then \(g\) also has a root and so it too factors, and so on.
  2. \(\Rightarrow\) (3): Say \(L \subseteq E\) is algebraic. Pick \(\a \in E\text{.}\) Then \(\a\) is a root of some \(f(x) \in F[x]\text{.}\) But since \(f\) factors completely, \(\a \in L\text{.}\)
  3. \(\Rightarrow\) (1). Pick a non-constant \(f(x) \in L[x]\text{.}\) By [provisional cross-reference: cite] , there there is finite extension \(L'\) of \(L\) in which \(f\) does have a root. By assumption \(L = L'\) and so this root must be in \(L\text{.}\)

Definition 16.62. Algebraic Closure.

Given a field \(F\text{,}\) a field \(\ov{F}\) is called an algebraic closure of \(F\) if \(\ov{F}\) is an algebraic field extension of \(F\) and \(\ov{F}\) is algebraically closed.

Example 16.63.

\(\C\) is an algebraic closure of \(\R\text{.}\) This follows from the fact that \(\R \subseteq \C\) is a finite extension, hence algebraic, and the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra, which we will not prove.

Proof.

It is far from clear that \(\ov{F}\) is a subfield of \(L\text{,}\) and so we first prove that: Given \(\a, \beta \in \ov{F}\text{,}\) we have that \([F(\a): F]\) and \([F(\a, \beta): F(\a)]\) are finite and hence so is \([F(\a, \beta): F]\text{.}\) Thus, every element of \(F(\a, \beta)\) is algebraic over \(F\text{;}\) that is, \(F(\a, \beta) \subseteq \ov{F}\text{.}\) Since \(F(\a, \beta)\) is a field, it follows that \(\ov{F}\) contains \(\a \pm \beta\text{,}\) \(\a \cdot \beta\) and \(\a^{-1}\) if \(\a \ne 0\text{.}\) This proves that \(\ov{F}\) is indeed a subfield of \(L\text{.}\)
It is clear from the definition that \(F \subseteq \ov{F}\) is an algebraic field extension.
Given a non-constant \(g(x) \in \ov{F}[x]\text{,}\) let \(\a\) be one of its roots in \(L\) (which exists since we assume \(L\) is algebraically closed). Then \(\ov{F} \subseteq \ov{F}(\a)\) is an algebraic extension and hence so is \(F \subseteq \ov{F}(\a)\) by Proposition . This proves \(\a \in \ov{F}\) and hence that \(\ov{F}\) is algebraically closed.

Proof.

Fake Proof of Existence:
Let \(\cS\) be the collection of all algebraic field extensions of \(F\text{.}\) Make \(\cS\) into a poset by declaring \(L \leq L'\) iff \(L \subseteq L'\text{.}\) We prove \(\cS\) has a maximal element.
Let \(\cT\) be any totally ordered subset of \(\cS\text{.}\) If \(\cT\) is empty, then \(F \in \cS\) is an upper bound for \(\cT\text{.}\) If \(\cT\) is non-empty, set \(K := \cup_{E \in \cT} E\text{.}\) Using that \(\cT\) is totally ordered, it is not hard to see that \(K\) is indeed a field. It clearly contains \(F\) as a subfield and every element of it is algebraic over \(F\text{.}\) So \(K \in \cS\) and it is an upper bound for \(\cT\text{.}\) By Zorn’s Lemma, \(\cS\) has a maximal member \(L\text{.}\)
By construction \(L\) is algebraic over \(F\text{.}\) If \(L\) were not algebraically closed, then there would be a non-trivial algebraic extension \(L \subsetneq E\) of it, by [provisional cross-reference: cite] . But then \(F \subseteq E\) is algebraic by Proposition [provisional cross-reference: cite], and this contradicts the maximality of \(L\text{.}\)
Why is this only a fake proof? It’s because \(\cS\text{,}\) as we’ve defined it, is not a set but rather it is something bigger than that. Zorn’s Lemma only applies to posets. How annoying!

Proof.

Let \(F \subseteq K\) be a finite extension of fields of degree \(n = [K : F ]\text{.}\)
Suppose that \(f \in F[x]\) is irreducible of degree \(d\) and \(\gcd(d, n) = 1\text{.}\)
First, note that if \(d=1\) then \(f(x)\) will remain irreducible in \(K[x]\) [provisional cross-reference: empty]. Suppose then that \(d>1\text{.}\) There exists an algebraically closed extension \(\widetilde F\) such that \(f\) has a root \(r\) [provisional cross-reference: empty]. Consider \(K(r)\text{.}\) As \(r\) is algebraic in \(K(r)\) we know there exists some unique irreducible minimum polynomial \(g\) of degree \(q\text{,}\) and thus that \([K(r):K]=q\) [provisional cross-reference: empty]. Using the The Degree Formula we see that
\begin{equation*} [K(r):F]=[K(r):K][K:F]=qn. \end{equation*}
However, \([K(r):F]=[K(r):F(r)][F(r):F]\) and so \(qn=md\) for some \(m\in\Z\text{,}\) so \(d|qn\text{.}\) As \(\gcd(n,d)=1\) we must have \(d|q\text{.}\) But \(q\) was defined to be the degree of \(g\text{,}\) which divides \(f\text{.}\) As \(d|q\) and \(q\leq d\text{,}\) we see that \(d=q\text{,}\) so \(f=kg\) for some \(k\in F\text{.}\) As irreducible polynomials multiplied by a constant are still irreducible, we see that \(f\) is indeed irreducible in \(K[x]\text{.}\)
The statement in part (a) would become false if the assumption that \(\gcd(n, d) = 1\) were omitted.

Example 16.67.

Let \(p(x)\) be a non-constant irreducible polynomial of degree \(d\) in \(F[x]\text{.}\) Let \(K=F[x]/p(x)\text{.}\) Because \(p(x)\) is irreducible and \(F[x]\) is a PID, \((p(x))\) is a maximal ideal. Thus \(K = F[x]/(p(x))\) is a field [provisional cross-reference: empty], \([K:F]=d\text{,}\) and \(x+p(x)\) is a root of \(p(x)\) in \(K\) [provisional cross-reference: empty]. Hence \(p(x)\) is no longer irreducible by Theorem 2.2

Qual Watch.

Proving Theorem 16.66 was [cross-reference to target(s) "jan-2023-7" missing or not unique] on the [cross-reference to target(s) "jan-2023" missing or not unique] qualifying exam and [cross-reference to target(s) "may-2017-7" missing or not unique] on the [cross-reference to target(s) "may-2017" missing or not unique] qualifying exam.